John stuart Mill
Comparison between Direct and Indirect Taxation
V.6.1
§1. Are direct or indirect taxes the most eligible? This question, at all times
interesting, has of late excited a considerable amount of discussion. In England
there is a popular feeling, of old standing, in favour of indirect, or it should
rather be said in opposition to direct, taxation. The feeling is not grounded on
the merits of the case, and is of a puerile kind. An Englishman dislikes, not so
much the payment, as the act of paying. He dislikes seeing the face of the
tax-collector, and being subjected to his peremptory demand. Perhaps, too, the
money which he is required to pay directly out of his pocket is the only
taxation which he is quite sure that he pays at all. That a tax of one shilling
per pound on tea, or of two shillings per bottle on wine, raises the price of
each pound of tea and bottle of wine which he consumes, by that and more than
that amount, cannot indeed be denied; it is the fact, and is intended to be so,
and he himself, at times, is perfectly aware of it; but it makes hardly any
impression on his practical feelings and associations, serving to illustrate the
distinction between what is merely known to be true and what is felt to be so.
The unpopularity of direct taxation, contrasted with the easy manner in which
the public consent to let themselves be fleeced in the prices of commodities,
has generated in many friends of improvement a directly opposite mode of
thinking to the foregoing. They contend that the very reason which makes direct
taxation disagreeable, makes it preferable. Under it, every one knows how much
he really pays; and if he votes for a war, or any other expensive national
luxury, he does so with his eyes open to what it costs him. If all taxes were
direct, taxation would be much more perceived than at present; and there would
be a security which now there is not, for economy in the public expenditure.
V.6.2
Although this argument is not without force, its weight is likely to be
constantly diminishing. The real incidence of indirect taxation is every day
more generally understood and more familiarly recognized: and whatever else may
be said of the changes which are taking place in the tendencies of the human
mind, it can scarcely, I think, be denied, that things are more and more
estimated according to their calculated value, and less according to their
non-essential accompaniments. The mere distinction between paying money directly
to the tax-collector, and contributing the same sum through the intervention of
the tea-dealer or the wine-merchant, no longer makes the whole difference
between dislike or opposition and passive acquiescence. But further, while any
such infirmity of the popular mind subsists, the argument grounded on it tells
partly on the other side of the question. If our present revenue of about
seventy [1862] millions were all raised by direct taxes, an extreme
dissatisfaction would certainly arise at having to pay so much; but while men's
minds are so little guided by reason, as such a change of feeling from so
irrelevant a cause would imply, so great an aversion to taxation might not be an
unqualified good. Of the seventy millions in question, nearly thirty are pledged,
under the most binding obligations, to those whose property has been borrowed
and spent by the state: and while this debt remains unredeemed, a greatly
increased impatience of taxation would involve no little danger of a breach of
faith, similar to that which, in the defaulting states of America, has been
produced, and in some of them still continues, from the same cause. That part,
indeed, of the public expenditure, which is devoted to the maintenance of civil
and military establishments, (that is, all except the interest of the national
debt) affords, in many of its details, ample scope for retrenchment.*50 But
while much of the revenue is wasted under the mere pretence of public service,
so much of the most important business of government is left undone, that
whatever can be rescued from useless expenditure is urgently required for useful.
Whether the object be education; a more efficient and accessible administration
of justice; reforms of any kind which, like the Slave Emancipation, require
compensation to individual interests; or what is as important as any of these,
the entertainment of a sufficient staff of able and educated public servants, to
conduct in a better than the present awkward manner the business of legislation
and administration; every one of these things implies considerable expense, and
many of them have again and again been prevented by the reluctance which existed
to apply to Parliament for an increased grant of public money, though (besides
that the existing means would probably be sufficient if applied to the proper
purposes) the cost would be repaid, often a hundredfold, in mere pecuniary
advantage to the community generally. If so great an addition were made to the
public dislike of taxation as might be the consequence of confining it to the
direct form, the classes who profit by the misapplication of public money might
probably succeed in saving that by which they profit, at the expense of that
which would only be useful to the public.
V.6.3
There is, however, a frequent plea in support of indirect taxation, which must
be altogether rejected, as grounded on a fallacy. We are often told that taxes
on commodities are less burthensome than other taxes, because the contributor
can escape from them by ceasing to use the taxed commodity. He certainly can, if
that be his object, deprive the government of the money: but he does so by a
sacrifice of his own indulgences, which (if he chose to undergo it) would
equally make up to him for the same amount taken from him by direct taxation.
Suppose a tax laid on wine, sufficient to add five pounds to the price of the
quantity of wine which he consumes in a year. He has only (we are told) to
diminish his consumption of wine by 5l., and he escapes the burthen. True: but
if the 5l., instead of being laid on wine, had been taken from him by an income
tax, he could, by expending 5l. less in wine, equally save the amount of the tax,
so that the difference between the two cases is really illusory. If the
government takes from the contributor five pounds a year, whether in one way or
another, exactly that amount must be retrenched from his consumption to leave
him as well off as before; and in either way the same amount of sacrifice,
neither more nor less, is imposed on him.
V.6.4
On the other hand, it is some advantage on the side of indirect taxes, that what
they exact from the contributor is taken at a time and in a manner likely to be
convenient to him. It is paid at a time when he has at any rate a payment to
make; it causes, therefore, no additional trouble, nor (unless the tax be on
necessaries) any inconvenience but what is inseparable from the payment of the
amount. He can also, except in the case of very perishable articles, select his
own time for laying in a stock of the commodity, and consequently for payment of
the tax. The producer or dealer who advances these taxes, is, indeed, sometimes
subjected to inconvenience; but, in the case of imported goods, this
inconvenience is reduced to a minimum by what is called the Warehousing System,
under which, instead of paying the duty at the time of importation, he is only
required to do so when he takes out the goods for consumption, which is seldom
done until he has either actually found, or has the prospect of immediately
finding, a purchaser.
V.6.5
*51The strongest objection, however, to raising the whole or the greater part of
a large revenue by direct taxes, is the impossibility of assessing them fairly
without a conscientious co-operation on the part of the contributors, not to be
hoped for in the present low state of public morality. In the case of an income
tax, we have already seen that unless it be found practicable to exempt savings
altogether from the tax, the burthen cannot be apportioned with any tolerable
approach to fairness upon those whose incomes are derived from business or
professions; and this is in fact admitted by most of the advocates of direct
taxation, who, I am afraid, generally get over the difficulty by leaving those
classes untaxed, and confining their projected income tax to "realized property,"
in which form it certainly has the merit of being a very easy form of plunder.
But enough has been said in condemnation of this expedient. We have seen,
however, that a house-tax is a form of direct taxation not liable to the same
objections as an income tax, and indeed liable to as few objections of any kind
as perhaps any of our indirect taxes. But it would be impossible to raise by a
house tax alone, the greatest part of the revenue of Great Britain, without
producing a very objectionable overcrowding of the population, through the
strong motive which all persons would have to avoid the tax by restricting their
house accommodation. Besides, even a house tax has inequalities, and consequent
injustices; no tax is exempt from them, and it is neither just nor politic to
make all the inequalities fall in the same places, by calling upon one tax to
defray the whole or the chief part of the public expenditure. So much of the
local taxation, in this country, being already in the form of a house tax, it is
probable that ten millions a year would be fully as much as could beneficially
be levied, through this medium, for general purposes.
V.6.6
A certain amount of revenue may, as we have seen, be obtained without injustice
by a peculiar tax on rent. Besides the present land-tax, and an equivalent for
the revenue now derived from stamp duties on the conveyance of land, some
further taxation might, I have contended, at some future period be imposed, to
enable the state to participate in the progressive increase of the incomes of
landlords from natural causes. Legacies and inheritances, we have also seen,
ought to be subjected to taxation sufficient to yield a considerable revenue.
With these taxes, and a house tax of suitable amount; we should, I think, have
reached the prudent limits of direct taxation, save in a national emergency so
urgent as to justify the government in disregarding the amount of inequality and
unfairness which may ultimately be found inseparable from an income tax.*52 The
remainder of the revenue would have to be provided by taxes on consumption, and
the question is, which of these are the least objectionable.
V.6.7
§2. There are some forms of indirect taxation which must be peremptorily
excluded. Taxes on commodities, for revenue purposes, must not operate as
protecting duties, but must be levied impartially on every mode in which the
articles can be obtained, whether produced in the country itself or imported. An
exclusion must also be put upon all taxes on the necessaries of life, or on the
materials or instruments employed in producing those necessaries. Such taxes are
always liable to encroach on what should be left untaxed, the incomes barely
sufficient for healthful existence; and on the most favourable supposition,
namely, that wages rise to compensate the labourers for the tax, it operates as
a peculiar tax on profits, which is at once unjust, and detrimental to national
wealth.*53 What remain are taxes on luxuries. And these have some properties
which strongly recommend them. In the first place, they can never, by any
possibility, touch those whose whole income is expended on necessaries; while
they do reach those by whom what is required for necessaries, is expended on
indulgences. In the next place, they operate in some cases as an useful, and the
only useful, kind of sumptuary law. I disclaim all asceticism, and by no means
wish to see discouraged, either by law or opinion, any indulgence (consistent
with the means and obligations of the person using it) which is sought from a
genuine inclination for, and enjoyment of, the thing itself; but a great portion
of the expenses of the higher and middle classes in most countries, and the
greatest in this, is not incurred for the sake of the pleasure afforded by the
things on which the money is spent, but from regard to opinion, and an idea that
certain expenses are expected from them, as an appendage of station; and I
cannot but think that expenditure of this sort is a most desirable subject of
taxation. If taxation discourages it, some good is done, and if not, no harm;
for in so far as taxes are levied on things which are desired and possessed from
motives of this description, nobody is the worse for them. When a thing is
bought not for its use but for its costliness, cheapness is no recommendation.
As Sismondi remarks, the consequence of cheapening articles of vanity, is not
that less is expended on such things, but that the buyers substitute for the
cheapened article some other which is more costly, or a more elaborate quality
of the same thing; and as the inferior quality answered the purpose of vanity
equally well when it was equally expensive, a tax on the article is really paid
by nobody: it is a creation of public revenue by which nobody loses.*54
V.6.8
§3. In order to reduce as much as possible the inconveniences, and increase the
advantages, incident to taxes on commodities, the following are the practical
rules which suggest themselves. 1st. To raise as large a revenue as conveniently
may be, from those classes of luxuries which have most connexion with vanity,
and least with positive enjoyment; such as the more costly qualities of all
kinds of personal equipment and ornament. 2ndly. Whenever possible, to demand
the tax, not from the producer, but directly from the consumer, since when
levied on the producer it raises the price always by more, and often by much
more, than the mere amount of the tax. Most of the minor assessed taxes in this
country are recommended by both these considerations. But with regard to horses
and carriages, as there are many persons to whom, from health or constitution,
these are not so much luxuries as necessaries, the tax paid by those who have
but one riding horse, or but one carriage, especially of the cheaper
descriptions, should be low; while taxation should rise very rapidly with the
number of horses and carriages, and with their costliness. 3rdly. But as the
only indirect taxes which yield a large revenue are those which fall on articles
of universal or very general consumption, and as it is therefore necessary to
have some taxes on real luxuries, that is, on things which afford pleasure in
themselves, and are valued on that account rather than for their cost; these
taxes should, if possible, be so adjusted as to fall with the same proportional
weight on small, on moderate, and on large incomes. This is not an easy matter;
since the things which are the subjects of the more productive taxes, are in
proportion more largely consumed by the poorer members of the community than by
the rich. Tea, coffee, sugar, tobacco, fermented drinks, can hardly be so taxed
that the poor shall not bear more than their due share of the burthen. Something
might be done by making the duty on the superior qualities, which are used by
the richer consumers, much higher in proportion to the value (instead of much
lower, as is almost universally the practice, under the present [1848] English
system); but in some cases the difficulty of at all adjusting the duty to the
value, so as to prevent evasion, is said, with what truth I know not, to be
insuperable; so that it is thought necessary to levy the same fixed duty on all
the qualities alike: a flagrant injustice to the poorer class of contributors,
unless compensated by the existence of other taxes from which, as from the
present income tax, they are altogether exempt. 4thly. As far as is consistent
with the preceding rules, taxation should rather be concentrated on a few
articles than diffused over many, in order that the expenses of collection may
be smaller, and that as few employments as possible may be burthensomely and
vexatiously interfered with. 5thly. Among luxuries of general consumption,
taxation should by preference attach itself to stimulants, because these, though
in themselves as legitimate indulgences as any others, are more liable than most
others to be used in excess, so that the check to consumption, naturally arising
from taxation, is on the whole better applied to them than to other things.
6thly. As far as other considerations permit, taxation should be confined to
imported articles, since these can be taxed with a less degree of vexatious
interference, and with fewer incidental bad effects, than when a tax is levied
on the field or on the workshop. Custom-duties are, cæteris paribus, much less
objectionable than excise: but they must be laid only on things which either
cannot, or at least will not, be produced in the country itself; or else their
production there must be prohibited (as in England is the case with tobacco), or
subjected to an excise duty of equivalent amount. 7thly. No tax ought to be kept
so high as to furnish a motive to its evasion, too strong to be counteracted by
ordinary means of prevention: and especially no commodity should be taxed so
highly as to raise up a class of lawless characters, smugglers, illicit
distillers, and the like.
V.6.9
Of the excise and custom duties lately existing in this country, all which are
intrinsically unfit to form part of a good system of taxation, have, since the
last reforms by Mr. Gladstone, been got rid of.*55 Among these are all duties on
ordinary articles of food,*56 whether for human beings or for cattle; those on
timber, as falling on the materials of lodging, which is one of the necessaries
of life; all duties on the metals, and on implements made of them; taxes on
soap, which is a necessary of cleanliness, and on tallow, the material both of
that and of some other necessaries; the tax on paper, an indispensable
instrument of almost all business and of most kinds of instruction. The duties
which now yield nearly the whole of the customs and excise revenue, those on
sugar, coffee, tea, wine, beer, spirits, and tobacco, are in themselves where a
large amount of revenue is necessary, extremely proper taxes; but at present
grossly unjust, from the disproportionate weight with which they press on the
poorer classes; and some of them (those on spirits and tobacco) are so high as
to cause a considerable*57 amount of smuggling. It is probable that most of
these taxes might bear a great reduction without any material loss of revenue.
In what manner the finer articles of manufacture, consumed by the rich, might
most advantageously be taxed, I must leave to be decided by those who have the
requisite practical knowledge. The difficulty would be, to effect it without an
inadmissible degree of interference with production. In countries which, like
the United States, import the principal part of the finer manufactures which
they consume, there is little difficulty in the matter: and even where nothing
is imported but the raw material, that may be taxed, especially the qualities of
it which are exclusively employed for the fabrics used by the richer class of
consumers. Thus, in England a high custom-duty on raw silk would be consistent
with principle; and it might perhaps be practicable to tax the finer qualities
of cotton or linen yarn, whether spun in the country itself or imported.
Notes for this chapter
50.
[So since the 3rd ed. (1852). According to the original text, the expenditure on
civil and military establishments was "still in many cases unnecessarily
profuse, but though many of the items will bear great reduction, others
certainly require increase," and the hope was not held out, as in the
parenthesis also inserted further on in the paragraph in the 3rd ed., that
retrenchment would provide sufficient means for the new purposes.]
51.
[The present text of the first two sentences of this paragraph dates from the
3rd ed. (1852). The original (1848) ran:
"The decisive objection, however, to raising the whole or the greater part of a
large revenue by direct taxes, is the impossibility of assessing them fairly. In
the case of an income-tax, I have pointed out that the burthen can never be
apportioned with any tolerable approach to fairness upon those whose incomes are
derived from a business or profession."]
52.
[So since the 3rd ed. (1852). The original ran: "in disregarding the inequality
and unfairness inseparable from every practicable form of income tax."]
Book V. Chapter VI. Section 2
53.
Some argue that the materials and instruments of all production should be exempt
from taxation; but these, when they do not enter into the production of
necessaries, seem as proper subjects of taxation as the finished article. It is
chiefly with reference to foreign trade that such taxes have been considered
injurious. Internationally speaking, they may be looked upon as export duties,
and, unless in cases in which an export duty is advisable, they should be
accompanied with an equivalent drawback on exportation. But there is no
sufficient reason against taxing the materials and instruments used in the
production of anything which is itself a fit object of taxation.
54.
"Were we to suppose that diamonds could only be procured from one particular and
distant country, and pearls from another, and were the produce of the mines in
the former, and of the fishery in the latter, from the operation of natural
causes, to become doubly difficult to procure, the effect would merely be that
in time half the quantity of diamonds and pearls would be sufficient to mark a
certain opulence and rank, that it had before been necessary to employ for that
purpose. The same quantity of gold or some commodity reducible at last to labour,
would be required to produce the now reduced amount, as the former larger amount.
Were the difficulty interposed by the regulations of legislators... . . it could
make no difference to the fitness of these articles to serve the purposes of
vanity." Suppose that means were discovered whereby the physiological process
which generates the pearl might be induced ad libitum, the result being that the
amount of labour expended in procuring each pearl came to be only the
five-hundredth part of what it was before. "The ultimate effect of such a change
would depend on whether the fishery were free or not. Were it free to all, as
pearls could be got simply for the labour of fishing for them, a string of them
might be had for a few pence. The very poorest class of society could therefore
afford to decorate their persons with them. They would thus soon become
extremely vulgar and unfashionable, and so at last valueless. If however we
suppose that instead of the fishery being free, the legislator owns and has
complete command of the place, where alone pearls are to be procured; as the
progress of discovery advanced, he might impose a duty on them equal to the
diminution of labour necessary to procure them. They would then be as much
esteemed as they were before. What simple beauty they have would remain
unchanged. The difficulty to be surmounted in order to obtain them would be
different, but equally great, and they would therefore equally serve to mark the
opulence of those who possessed them." The net revenue obtained by such a tax "would
not cost the society anything. If not abused in its application, it would be a
clear addition of so much to the resources of the community."—Rae, New
Principles of Political Economy, pp. 369-71. [Sociological Theory of Capital,
pp. 286-88.]
55.
[So since the 5th ed. (1862). The original (1848) ran: "Among the excise and
custom duties now existing in this country, some must, on the principles we have
laid down, be altogether condemned."]
Book V. Chapter VI. Section 3
56.
[The footnote added to the 6th ed. (1865) was omitted from the 7th (1871): "Except
the shilling per quarter duty on corn, ostensibly for registration, and scarcely
felt as a burthen."]
57.
[So since 5th ed. (1862). In the original: "enormous."]
Book V. Chapter VII. Section 1